第 1 节
作者:朝令夕改      更新:2023-08-22 20:44      字数:9322
  Menexenus
  by Plato
  Translated by Benjamin Jowett
  APPENDIX I。
  It seems impossible to separate by any exact line the genuine writings of
  Plato from the spurious。  The only external evidence to them which is of
  much value is that of Aristotle; for the Alexandrian catalogues of a
  century later include manifest forgeries。  Even the value of the
  Aristotelian authority is a good deal impaired by the uncertainty
  concerning the date and authorship of the writings which are ascribed to
  him。  And several of the citations of Aristotle omit the name of Plato; and
  some of them omit the name of the dialogue from which they are taken。
  Prior; however; to the enquiry about the writings of a particular author;
  general considerations which equally affect all evidence to the genuineness
  of ancient writings are the following:  Shorter works are more likely to
  have been forged; or to have received an erroneous designation; than longer
  ones; and some kinds of composition; such as epistles or panegyrical
  orations; are more liable to suspicion than others; those; again; which
  have a taste of sophistry in them; or the ring of a later age; or the
  slighter character of a rhetorical exercise; or in which a motive or some
  affinity to spurious writings can be detected; or which seem to have
  originated in a name or statement really occurring in some classical
  author; are also of doubtful credit; while there is no instance of any
  ancient writing proved to be a forgery; which combines excellence with
  length。  A really great and original writer would have no object in
  fathering his works on Plato; and to the forger or imitator; the 'literary
  hack' of Alexandria and Athens; the Gods did not grant originality or
  genius。  Further; in attempting to balance the evidence for and against a
  Platonic dialogue; we must not forget that the form of the Platonic writing
  was common to several of his contemporaries。  Aeschines; Euclid; Phaedo;
  Antisthenes; and in the next generation Aristotle; are all said to have
  composed dialogues; and mistakes of names are very likely to have occurred。
  Greek literature in the third century before Christ was almost as
  voluminous as our own; and without the safeguards of regular publication;
  or printing; or binding; or even of distinct titles。  An unknown writing
  was naturally attributed to a known writer whose works bore the same
  character; and the name once appended easily obtained authority。  A
  tendency may also be observed to blend the works and opinions of the master
  with those of his scholars。  To a later Platonist; the difference between
  Plato and his imitators was not so perceptible as to ourselves。  The
  Memorabilia of Xenophon and the Dialogues of Plato are but a part of a
  considerable Socratic literature which has passed away。  And we must
  consider how we should regard the question of the genuineness of a
  particular writing; if this lost literature had been preserved to us。
  These considerations lead us to adopt the following criteria of
  genuineness:  (1) That is most certainly Plato's which Aristotle attributes
  to him by name; which (2) is of considerable length; of (3) great
  excellence; and also (4) in harmony with the general spirit of the Platonic
  writings。  But the testimony of Aristotle cannot always be distinguished
  from that of a later age (see above); and has various degrees of
  importance。  Those writings which he cites without mentioning Plato; under
  their own names; e。g。 the Hippias; the Funeral Oration; the Phaedo; etc。;
  have an inferior degree of evidence in their favour。  They may have been
  supposed by him to be the writings of another; although in the case of
  really great works; e。g。 the Phaedo; this is not credible; those again
  which are quoted but not named; are still more defective in their external
  credentials。  There may be also a possibility that Aristotle was mistaken;
  or may have confused the master and his scholars in the case of a short
  writing; but this is inconceivable about a more important work; e。g。 the
  Laws; especially when we remember that he was living at Athens; and a
  frequenter of the groves of the Academy; during the last twenty years of
  Plato's life。  Nor must we forget that in all his numerous citations from
  the Platonic writings he never attributes any passage found in the extant
  dialogues to any one but Plato。  And lastly; we may remark that one or two
  great writings; such as the Parmenides and the Politicus; which are wholly
  devoid of Aristotelian (1) credentials may be fairly attributed to Plato;
  on the ground of (2) length; (3) excellence; and (4) accordance with the
  general spirit of his writings。  Indeed the greater part of the evidence
  for the genuineness of ancient Greek authors may be summed up under two
  heads only:  (1) excellence; and (2) uniformity of traditiona kind of
  evidence; which though in many cases sufficient; is of inferior value。
  Proceeding upon these principles we appear to arrive at the conclusion that
  nineteen…twentieths of all the writings which have ever been ascribed to
  Plato; are undoubtedly genuine。  There is another portion of them;
  including the Epistles; the Epinomis; the dialogues rejected by the
  ancients themselves; namely; the Axiochus; De justo; De virtute; Demodocus;
  Sisyphus; Eryxias; which on grounds; both of internal and external
  evidence; we are able with equal certainty to reject。  But there still
  remains a small portion of which we are unable to affirm either that they
  are genuine or spurious。  They may have been written in youth; or possibly
  like the works of some painters; may be partly or wholly the compositions
  of pupils; or they may have been the writings of some contemporary
  transferred by accident to the more celebrated name of Plato; or of some
  Platonist in the next generation who aspired to imitate his master。  Not
  that on grounds either of language or philosophy we should lightly reject
  them。  Some difference of style; or inferiority of execution; or
  inconsistency of thought; can hardly be considered decisive of their
  spurious character。  For who always does justice to himself; or who writes
  with equal care at all times?  Certainly not Plato; who exhibits the
  greatest differences in dramatic power; in the formation of sentences; and
  in the use of words; if his earlier writings are compared with his later
  ones; say the Protagoras or Phaedrus with the Laws。  Or who can be expected
  to think in the same manner during a period of authorship extending over
  above fifty years; in an age of great intellectual activity; as well as of
  political and literary transition?  Certainly not Plato; whose earlier
  writings are separated from his later ones by as wide an interval of
  philosophical speculation as that which separates his later writings from
  Aristotle。
  The dialogues which have been translated in the first Appendix; and which
  appear to have the next claim to genuineness among the Platonic writings;
  are the Lesser Hippias; the Menexenus or Funeral Oration; the First
  Alcibiades。  Of these; the Lesser Hippias and the Funeral Oration are cited
  by Aristotle; the first in the Metaphysics; the latter in the Rhetoric。
  Neither of them are expressly attributed to Plato; but in his citation of
  both of them he seems to be referring to passages in the extant dialogues。
  From the mention of 'Hippias' in the singular by Aristotle; we may perhaps
  infer that he was unacquainted with a second dialogue bearing the same
  name。  Moreover; the mere existence of a Greater and Lesser Hippias; and of
  a First and Second Alcibiades; does to a certain extent throw a doubt upon
  both of them。  Though a very clever and ingenious work; the Lesser Hippias
  does not appear to contain anything beyond the power of an imitator; who
  was also a careful student of the earlier Platonic writings; to invent。
  The motive or leading thought of the dialogue may be detected in Xen。 Mem。;
  and there is no similar instance of a 'motive' which is taken from Xenophon
  in an undoubted dialogue of Plato。  On the other hand; the upholders of the
  genuineness of the dialogue will find in the Hippias a true Socratic
  spirit; they will compare the Ion as being akin both in subject and
  treatment; they will urge the authority of Aristotle; and they will detect
  in the treatment of the Sophist; in the satirical reasoning upon Homer; in
  the reductio ad absurdum of the doctrine that vice is ignorance; traces of
  a Platonic authorship。  In reference to the last point we are doubtful; as
  in some of the other dialogues; whether the author is asserting or
  overthrowing the paradox of Socrates; or merely following the argument
  'whither the wind blows。'  That no conclusion is arrived at is also in
  accordance with the character of the earlier dialogues。  The resemblances
  or imitations of the Gorgias; Protagoras; and Euthydemus; which have been
  observed in the Hippias; cannot with certainty be adduced on either side of
  the argument。